Updating the Abstract-Concrete Distinction in Ancient Near Eastern Numbers

CDLJ 2018:1

Cuneiform Digital Library Journal (ISSN: 1540-8779)

Published on 2021-06-18

© Cuneiform Digital Library Initiative

Creative Commons License This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License except when noted otherwise and in the case of artifact images which follow the CDLI terms of use.

Karenleigh A. Overmann

leee0vermann@gmail.com

University of Colorado, Colorado Springs

Keywords
Ancient Near East, numeracy, abstract, concrete, numbers

Abstract
The characterization of early token-based accounting using a concrete concept of number, later numerical notations an abstract one, has become well entrenched in the literature. After reviewing its history and assumptions, this article challenges the abstract-concrete distinction, presenting an alternative view of change in Ancient Near Eastern number concepts, wherein numbers are abstract from their inception and materially bound when most elaborated. The alternative draws on the chronological sequence of material counting technologies used in the Ancient Near East—fingers, tallies, tokens, and numerical notations—as reconstructed through archaeological and textual evidence and as interpreted through Material Engagement Theory, an extended-mind framework in which materiality plays an active role (Malafouris 2013).

§1. Introduction[*]
Early token-based accounting has long been understood as involving a “concrete” concept of number, with the invention of writing enabling the development of an “abstract” or “second-order” number concept (e.g., Damerow 1996a). This distinction between “abstract” and “concrete” numbers is thought to have been facilitated by the invention of writing, which enabled the separate representation of quantity (by means of numerical signs) from commodity (by means of graphic labels), information that had previously been conjoined in the shapes, sizes, and quantities of clay tokens (Schmandt-Besserat 1992a). In this familiar account, an abstract concept of number was presumably something the Mesopotamians not only lacked but were incapable of achieving before writing was invented. As expressed in the literature, “tokens reflected an archaic mode of ‘concrete’ counting prior to the invention of abstract numbers. This is supported by the fact that there are no tokens to express abstractly numbers such as ‘1’ or ‘10’. Instead, a particular counter was needed to account for each type of goods: Jars of oil were counted with ovoids, small measures of grain with cones, and large measures of grain with spheres” (Schmandt-Besserat 1992a: 6). Similarly, “[p]rior to the invention of the sexagesimal place value system [in the late 3rd millennium], there was no concept of abstract numeration: numbers were thought of not as independent entities but as attributes of concrete objects—the length of a line, for instance, or the quantity of sheep in a flock” (Robson 2007: 75).

§1.2. The abstract-concrete distinction has become fairly entrenched in the literature on Ancient Near Eastern numbers and thinking: “[T]he litany is often repeated that the Mesopotamians were incapable of abstract thought, that their languages lacked terms to express concepts” like numbers (Glassner 2000: 55). It is particularly associated with the extensive research and publication on Neolithic tokens by archaeologist Denise Schmandt-Besserat (e.g., 1977, 1978, 1982, 1986, 1992a, 1992b, 2010, 2016), as well as the cognitive analyses by developmental psychologist Peter Damerow (1988, 1996a, 1996b, 2007, 2010, 2012), who explicitly rooted the concrete-to-abstract notion in the work of psychologist Jean Piaget. Drawing in particular on work by sociologist Lucien Lévy-Bruhl (e.g., 1910, 1927), Piaget applied his ideas on cognitive development in children (e.g., how the thinking of children differs from that of adults; how the latter progressively develops from the former) to entire societies. These he divided into two groups. In the first were traditional and archaic societies, whose “prélogique” he compared to the “mentalité enfantine”; the second included his own and similar Western societies, labeled rational for their purported logical, adult thinking (Piaget 1928: 191-194). Such characterizations, pervasive in 19th-century discourse on cross-cultural differences in general and number systems in particular (e.g., Conant 1896), have been considered untenable since the mid-20th century, not merely for their perjoration but also for the overt biases that subvert their conclusions.

§1.3. If its basis is now terminologically and methodologically inapt, the idea that Ancient Near Eastern numbers were concrete before becoming abstract nonetheless labels real phenomena of change in the way numbers would have been conceptualized between the Neolithic (8300 to 4500 BC) and the Old Babylonian period (1900 to 1600 BC). One of the most significant changes was the separation of the representation of number from that of commodity in the late 4th millennium (Schmandt-Besserat 1992a; also see Friberg 1994; Malafouris 2010; Mattessich 1994), which enabled the further elaboration of notations and pictographs into a complex mathematics and literate writing. By the 2nd millennium, the Old Babylonian mathematicians had developed a so-called pure mathematics involving complex algorithms for calculating answers to artificial as well as practical problems (Friberg 2007; Høyrup 2002a, 2002b; Robson 2007, 2008). However, they do not appear to have speculated much about the nature of number as a concept, an inquiry that would be taken up by the Greek philosophers in the 1st millennium (Damerow 1996a, 1996b; Høyrup 1994; Klein 1968).

§1.4. While its pervasiveness in the literature and association with unambiguous conceptual change make the abstract-concrete distinction difficult to challenge, the need to update it is both apparent and overdue for several reasons. First, as mentioned, applying Piaget’s theory of cognitive ontogenesis to the development of societal thinking has fallen out of fashion, a reason in and of itself to reexamine its application to change in the conceptualization of Ancient Near East numbers. Second, the distinction has generated a number of related assumptions (e.g., that tokens were the first technology used for counting; that tokens were used in one-to-one correspondence with the things they counted, and without number-words) that can and should be reexamined once their Piagetian underpinning has been removed, especially in light of evidence suggesting precursor technologies and the complexity of structure reflected by the tokens themselves. Finally and perhaps most importantly, the abstract-concrete distinction may underestimate the role of materiality in structuring and changing how numbers are conceptualized. This misses the opportunity provided by the Ancient Near Eastern sequence of counting devices, which spanned the realization of initial number concepts to their elaboration into one of the ancient world’s great mathematical traditions, ultimately contributing to the modern conceptualization of number. Analysis of the sequence may shed new light on the changes characterized by the abstract-concrete distinction and perhaps the way materiality functions in human cognition more broadly.

§1.5. The challenge, then, is to update the abstract-concrete distinction in a way that both respects historical scholarship and provides new insight into the phenomena it characterized. After reviewing the history of the abstract-concrete distinction, an alternative view of change in Ancient Near Eastern numbers will be presented, one that encompasses materiality as a constitutive part of the cognitive system for numbers, and in which numbers are abstract from their inception and materially bound at their most elaborated. This alternative view of how numerical thinking is structured and changes over time draws on the sequence of material counting technologies used in the Ancient Near East, as reconstructed through archaeological and textual evidence (Overmann 2016a) and as interpreted through Material Engagement Theory, an extended-mind framework in which materiality plays an active role as a component of cognition with the ability to influence behavioral and psychological change (agency) and acquire and instantiate meaning (semiotic function) (Malafouris 2013). The alternative corresponds well to Damerow’s (1988) insight that the conceptualization of numbers was informed by their material representations, as well as his concern that developmental psychology, especially as it had been applied to historical-cultural development by Piaget, might not be ideal for understanding change in the conceptualization of number (also see discussion in Nicolopoulou 1997).

§2. The Piagetian Roots of the Abstract-Concrete Distinction
§2.1.
Piaget was a clinical psychologist best known for his work on cognitive development in children. In his theory of how adult cognition develops from childish thinking, Piaget asserted that children of any and all cultures pass through four ontogenetic stages: a sensorimotor stage (0-2 years) characterized by experiencing the world through sensation and movement; a preoperational stage (2-7 years) characterized by the lack of concrete logic or the ability to manipulate information mentally; a concrete operational stage (7-12 years) characterized by logical thinking limited to matters that involved physical manipulation; and a formal operational stage (12+ years) characterized by abstract thought, metacognition, and complex problem solving (Inhelder & Piaget 1958; Piaget 1937, 1952). (Follow-on elaboration and enhancement of Piaget’s work on cognitive ontogenesis, known as Neo-Piagetian theories, have added higher-order stages and sub-stages, not explicated here as tangential to the present argument.) Piaget held that the ontogenetic stages were necessarily progressive because the prior ones needed to be in place before any subsequent ones could develop. While scholars in the last half century have stopped applying Piaget’s theory to how societies think, his work on cognitive ontogenesis has remained influential in fields like developmental psychology and approaches like constructivism.

§2.2. For Piaget, societies possessed distinct mentalities, as did children and adults, which he called primitive for traditional or archaic societies and rational, scientific, or civilized for modern, industrialized ones. He asserted the so-called primitive mentality of the “civilisations inférieures” resembled the “mentalité enfantine” (Piaget 1928: 200-201) in several respects:

On peut citer comme exemples la tendance à l’affirmation sans preuve, le caractère affectif de la pensée, son caractère global, non analytique (le syncrétisme), l’absence de cohérence logique (des principes de contradiction et d’identité considérés comme des structures formelles), la difficulté à manier le raisonnement déductif et la fréquence des raisonnements par identification immédiate (participation), la causalité mystique, l’indifférenciation du psychique et du physique, la confusion du signe et de la cause, du signe et de la chose signifiée, etc. Nous ne prétendons nullement, cela va sans dire, que chacun de ces traits se présente de la même manière chez le primitif et l’enfant, et il faudrait un volume pour marquer les nuances, pour souligner l’aspect fonctionnel des ressemblances et écarter les identifications brutales. Mais, dans les grandes lignes, nous pensons qu’il y a des analogies. (Piaget 1928: 194)

Piaget also identified separate mechanisms for each, with “tradition sociale” constraining the primitive mentality and “l’égocentrisme de la pensée” that of the child, and these constituted “l’obstacle principal à la mise en parallèle du primitif et de l’enfant” (Piaget 1928: 192).

§2.3. Piaget was addressing the important question of how societies derived truth from opinion, the development of societal thinking that involves, as ontogeny does, the acquisition of concepts and the construction of structures of thought. He was not wrong about there being similarities between the two processes: Both involve interactivity with social others and the physical world, both are progressive in the sense that later constructions depend on previous ones, and both produce cognitive outcomes that are relatively consistent when viewed across individuals and societies. Some similarity is to be expected, given that any society is composed of individuals enculturated from birth to reproduce and transmit its behaviors, knowledge, and manner of thinking. However, while Piaget differentiated mechanisms of social constraint and egocentrism, he does not appear to have made a similar distinction between the child’s acquisition of existing social knowledge, which entails the preexistence of concepts, terminology, and knowledgeable others, from its social invention, where new knowledge is generated and adult activity dominates discovery, transmission, and conventionalization (indeed, since the developmental acquisition of number involves ontogenetic maturation, children are unlikely to be a significant factor in numerical elaboration, though the requirement to explain things in terms they can understand may plausibly relate, at least in some small part, to numerical explication). The processes overlap, as invention involves knowledge and skills acquired when young that are perhaps ontogenetically organized in ways that facilitate creativity (e.g., analogous to the way children turn pidgin into creole), and both adults and children participate in the transmission and conventionalization of new knowledge.[1]

§2.4. The similarities and overlaps between the child’s acquisition of existing knowledge and a society’s generation of new knowledge may have further relevance to the history of thought (Oesterdiekhoff 2016). Here it suffices to acknowledge that Ancient Near Eastern children would have acquired knowledge of, behaviors associated with, and ways of thinking about numbers both informally (e.g., via their exposure to numbers as lexical and grammatical features of language; through their everyday use of numbers) and formally (as part of scribal training) and that this was likely to have informed the social elaboration of numerical concepts, even as increasing elaboration may have pushed acquisition toward greater formality. However, the present focus is not the child’s acquisition of number concepts but how the concepts themselves changed over time as a body of social knowledge, Damerow’s concern.

§3. Damerow’s Application of Piagetian Theory to Ancient Near Eastern Numbers
§3.1.
In researching ancient mathematics, Damerow deserves credit for advancing the understanding of early Mesopotamian numerical systems through his methodical analysis of the extant data. This helped elevate the topic from the dismissive treatment it more commonly received from mathematical hands, where Babylonian and Egyptian contributions have often been considered rudimentary and “almost insignificant” in comparison to those of the later Greeks: These mathematical traditions were the merest “scrawling of children just learning how to write as opposed to great literature,” castigated as much for their practical application and empirical and inductive methodology as for making “hardly any progress [over a period of 4000 years]” and “[lacking] the spirit of mathematics” (Kline 1967: 14). In contrast, the excitement with which Damerow (and indeed, predecessors, contemporaries, and successors that include Thureau-Dangin (1921), Neugebauer (1957), Vogel (1959), Vaiman (1961); Marvin Powell, Jöran Friberg, Jens Høyrup, Hans J. Nissen, Robert K. Englund, Eleanor Robson, Christine Proust, and Grégory Chambon) investigated the methods, context, and results of the Ancient Near Eastern mathematical tradition was a significant force in motivating scholarly interest from the historical and psychological perspectives.

§3.2. Damerow analyzed numerical changes from the Paleolithic to the modern age, targeting those that occurred in the Ancient Near East between the Neolithic, which encompassed the invention of agriculture, significant increases in population, and the intensification of sedentism, specialization, stratification, and interconnectedness, and the Bronze Age, which oversaw the development of a complex mathematics and literary tradition. Distinctive technologies are associated with each: clay tokens with the Neolithic, numerical notations the Bronze Age. These were intermediated by forms that resembled tokens—numerical impressions and archaic numerical notations—whose resemblance attests to the numerical meaning of the tokens (at least the plain ones used in 4th-millennium accounting—spheres, cones, disks, cylinders, and tetrahedra; Friberg 1994), and whose use (and the subsequent development of pictographic labels for the commodities they enumerated) are widely credited as constituting the invention of writing. In characterizing numerical change using Piaget’s theory of societal mentalities, Damerow associated the numerical notations with an abstract concept of number. This necessitated that the earlier technologies and the societies that used them, like Piagetian traditional societies, were concrete and associated with difficulty distinguishing sign (e.g., tokens) from signified (the objects they counted). Damerow wrote that the Neolithic bore “the closest resemblance with what we know from extant indigenous cultures at a stone age level. If, therefore, Piaget’s assumption is correct that cognition in such cultures does not exceed the preoperative level, then the Neolithic Revolution in spite of the material progress did not fundamentally change the level of cognition achieved at the end of the Paleolithic Period” (Damerow 1996b: 18).table 1

Table 1: Damerow’s model of conceptual development in ancient Near Eastern numbers

§3.3. Damerow advocated a four-stage model of Ancient Near Eastern numeracy, with the two highest stages each divided into two sub-stages (1996a: 139–148; also see Table 1): Stage 0 was pre-arithmetical quantification “defined by the absence of any arithmetical activities”; Stage 1 was proto-arithmetical quantification that began “with the construction of one-to-one correspondences.” Stage 2 consisted of symbol-based arithmetic “based on the manipulation of symbols according to rules derived from the construction of second-order representations of quantities and actions,” with second-order representations indicating “thoughts about thoughts”; Stage 2A involved context-dependent symbol systems with “no general system of abstract number notations,” while Stage 2B involved abstract symbol systems “no longer dependent on any specific contexts of application.” Finally, Stage 3 consisted of concept-based arithmetic “defined by the construction of second-order representations of symbolic arithmetical transformations by means of mental reflection”; Stage 3A involved natural-language derivations “composed of statements and arguments encoded in natural language” with “explicitly defined” concepts of number, of which the “best-known early instances” came from ancient Greek mathematics, while Stage 3B involved symbolic derivations in which “the encoding of concepts in natural language [was] replaced by encoding in abstract symbol systems ... [with concepts] subsumed under generalized, unifying concepts,” a progression “not completed before the end of the nineteenth century” AD.

§3.4. It is possible to agree with Damerow regarding the overall progression and relative chronology of his model, since numerical elaboration in later stages depends on numerical concepts in some form or another being available in earlier ones. Some of the model’s timeline and characterizations are undoubtedly correct, as the representational separation of number and commodity was an abstraction that potentialized their further elaboration; Greek philosophers were indeed concerned, as Old Babylonian mathematicians appear not to have been, with the ontological status of number (Høyrup 1994; Klein 1968); and the emergence of generalized, unifying mathematical concepts relatively recently is historical fact (Gowers 2008). Nonetheless, this partial acceptance does not preclude rejecting the ideas that tokens were confused with the objects they enumerated or that they represented concrete numbers while written notations meant abstract ones. Further, the mechanism of change in societal thinking may not have been ontogenetic maturity but, as argued here, material engagement: Numerical content and structure were influenced by the material forms used for counting, associated behaviors, and psychological processing related to the acquisition of an elaborated cultural system. That is, conceptual change, and perhaps change in psychological processing as well, would have occurred through change in the materials used to represent and manipulate numbers. Material engagement also provides a mechanism for conceptual structuring and change at the level of both individual and society without needing to appeal to ontogenesis for either.

§3.5. Damerow’s model also inherited some of the shortfalls of Piagetian theory: For example, Piaget’s research in ontogenetic development and numerical acquisition focused on children enculturated into numerate Western societies, generating findings whose cross-cultural generalizability has been convincingly challenged (e.g., Dasen 1994). To what degree the cultural elaboration of numbers influences their acquisition remains an open question, given that the perceptual ability to appreciate quantity, which governs how quantity is experienced and to some extent influences how numbers are cognized, appears stable across significant differences in numerical elaboration (Henrich, Heine & Norenzayan 2010). Generalizability of Piaget’s theory of societal mentalities faces similar difficulties: If indeed generalizable, Piagetian stages similar to those Damerow construed for Mesopotamian numbers should be found in Egypt, China, and Mesoamerica, the other ancient mathematical traditions, but they are not (Chrisomalis 2005). Moreover, the emergence of context-independent numerical representations from multiple systems of context-dependent ones marked for Damerow the critical transition to abstract numbers in the Ancient Near East. Fitting this into Piagetian theory meant excluding the possibility that the Neolithic cultural elaboration influenced how numbers were conceptualized, despite the likelihood that numbers both enabled and were themselves elaborated during the Neolithic Revolution, as there is a well-established (if poorly explained) cross-cultural correlation between numerical elaboration and the complexity of material culture generally (Epps et al. 2012).

§4. Abstract and Related Assumptions
§4.1.
The distribution of numerical meaning across multiple number systems in the early numerical signs (i.e., the tokens, numerical impressions, and archaic notations) made their value context-dependent and also specified the commodity they counted. Damerow assumed this necessarily marked the absence of an abstract concept of number. As this meant there were no abstract number concepts needing linguistic expression, it was also assumed that the early numerical signs coexisted with a restricted numerical lexicon (i.e., one in which it was possible to count no higher than 20 and perhaps no higher than 3 or 4; Comrie 2013). Finally, tokens are often discussed as if they were the first counting technology and were used in one-to-one correspondence with the objects they counted. These assumptions are closely related to one another and to the various ways the term abstract has been used in the literature, which will be examined first: Abstract can refer to a concept formed or changed through the cognitive process of abstraction. The term can also have the sense of something intangible; that no longer faithfully resembles what it intends to depict; that has become distilled, truer, or rarified; that is theoretical rather than practical when applied; or a number that is unspecified in not referring to any particular object. After these are examined, an additional way of understanding abstract as the distribution of a concept over multiple material forms, and hence, its seeming independence from any particular form, will be offered.

§4.2. As a cognitive ability, abstraction is a process of concept formation and change that encompasses generalization (identifying properties common to sets of objects; inducting from particulars; applying inductive insights to new domains), decontextualization (extracting content from its original circumstances to remove their influence on its meaning), synthesis (combining parts into wholes, often in such a way that sums are greater than the parts), and reification (reinterpreting processes or relations as permanent entities in their own right, making them available to act as inputs to other processes or relations) (Dreyfus 1991; Ferrari 2003; Sfard & Linchevski 1994). As a process, abstraction is as much behavioral and material as it is mental. For example, numbers begin as a recognition that sets of objects share quantity (Russell 1920), generalization occasioned by behaviors like one-to-one correspondence that manipulate sets of objects into arrangements whereby their shared quantity can be appreciated. Change in the venue for counting—performing it in a place different from the one where the enumerated goods are located—would decontextualize counters from counted. And blank space in the sexagesimal place value system developed in Mesopotamia toward the end of the 3rd millennium would be reified, first as a meta-sign for the absence of any number, and ultimately as a number in its own right, zero (Rotman 1987).

figure 1

Fig. 1: Model of a conceptual blend anchored and stabilized by a material form (adapted from Malafouris 2013, Fig. 5.2). Blending “operates on ... Input mental [and physical] spaces to yield a third space, the blend. The blend inherits partial structure from the input spaces and has emergent structure of its own” through processes like contextualization, recognition of inter-element relations, and elaboration (Fauconnier 1997: 149-151, emphasis original). The letters represent elements such as knowledge (mental), features (physical), and capacities (both). The lines between elements are “ontological correspondences [between internal (mental) and external (physical) domains that] primarily involve connections of identity, analogy, similarity, causality, change, time, intentionality, space, role, and part-whole, and in some cases also of representation” (Malafouris 2013: 100). Projection is triggered and supported by an “external manipulable structure” that interacts with and influences mental capabilities and conceptual content; it augments and contextualizes the observed material form with knowledge, attended features, construed relations, etc., thereby going “beyond what is immediately perceived” (Malafouris 2013: 102) to become “transformational and not merely informational” (di Paolo, Rohde & De Jaegher 2010: 39). Blending enables numerical intuitions to be made tangible, expressed, explicated, manipulated, and visualized.

§4.3. Schmandt-Besserat labeled objects thought to be numerical counters “tokens,” a term that invoked the type-token distinction of philosopher Charles Saunders Peirce. A Token is “a Single object or thing which is in some single place at any one instant of time, such … thing being significant only as occurring just when and where it does”; in comparison, a Type “is not a Single thing or Single event. It does not exist; it only determines things that do exist” (Peirce 1906: 506). Where a Peircean Token is tangible, a Type is not, making the former presumably concrete, the latter abstract. Abstract products need not inhabit the same phenomenological level, as a (physical) drawing of a triangle differs from the (ideal) geometrical concept of one. That is, the concepts realized by abstraction are “not concrete and tangible” (Gowers 2002: 16), a characterization often applied to mathematical objects. Formally, abstract objects are conceived as non-mental and nonsensible (e.g., Plato’s ideal forms) or as lacking spatiotemporal locus, causal efficacy, or both (Linnebo 2013; Rosen 2014). This is mathematical realism, the view that mathematical objects have an existence independent of the mind and sensible world. From a different perspective, being intangible or otherwise imperceptible is true of mental content, to anyone other than the person whose mental content it happens to be, unless it is made public some fashion (e.g., materially, linguistically, emotionally, etc.). Intangibility is implicit in intuitionism, the idea that numbers are intuited and mathematical objects mentally constructed (Brouwer 1981). The debate about whether numbers are mind-external or -internal need not be settled to recognize that either way, numbers would be intangibly abstract from their inception as comparisons of quantity between two sets of objects; their intangibility means that numbers depend on material instantiation for their expression, explication, manipulation, and visualization (Fig. 1). More interesting is the fact that they can be materially realized and systemically manipulated in the first place, as not every intangibly abstract concept or group of related concepts can as easily be (e.g., justice; societal norms). However, while conceptual content is related to the materiality that gives it form, there is arguably more to the former than the latter instantiates (were this not so, archaeological interpretation would be a much simpler matter). If the instantiating material makes the concept comprensible (Frege 1953), what its substance is (and is not) capable of has potential influence on the resultant content.

figure 2

Fig. 2: Chronology of numerical (top) and non-numerical (bottom) signs across five thousand years and multiple languages; both lineages descend from ancestral to modern forms, though not all intermediate forms or contributing branches are shown. The numerical sign shows greater conservation of form relative to the non-numerical sign, which reasonably relates to its non-phonetic semanticity. Over a similar time span (i.e., from the Shang oracle bones, through the Zhou, Qin, and Han writing reforms, to the 20th-century simplified script), Chinese non-numerical characters (not depicted here) show less orthographic change relative to the non-numerical example above, as they have not involved significant phonetic or semantic adaptation; however, Chinese non-numerical characters still show more change than the associated numerical signs (Branner 2006; Chrisomalis 2010; Martzloff 1997). Information compiled and images adapted from Chrisomalis 2010; Ifrah 2000; Nissen 1986; Tompack 1978; CDLI.

§4.4. A representation whose form has become relatively independent of the object it once depicted is abstract in the sense Schmandt-Besserat initially used: “Hypotheses about the origin of writing generally postulate an evolution from the concrete to the abstract: an initial pictographic stage that in the course of time and perhaps because of the carelessness of scribes becomes increasingly schematic” (1978: 50). Over several centuries, the pictographs used as archaic commodity labels did become less recognizable as the objects they depicted (Fig. 2), but probably not through inattention or neglect. Rather, decreased iconicity was an effect of emerging literacy: The neural reorganizations involved in recognizing handwritten written objects by their features relaxed the need to preserve the original iconic form; other contributing factors included motor habituation, biomechanical effectiveness, and visual discriminability (Overmann 2016b). Decreased iconicity also affects numerical signs (e.g., as the sign 2 was once two strokes), but to a lesser extent than non-numerical ones because of how they represent meaning and are organized systemically. Numerical signs can instantiate their meaning (Malafouris 2013), as two strokes or wedges are two. Even in abstract (e.g., 2) or symbolic form (as a small sphere meant an amount of N01 and a wedge meant 10), numerical signs are semantically meaningful without phonetic specification, a quality Powell (1971) noted Sumerian numbers share with modern Western numerals. This is because numerical signs share relations with each other and are organized in a limited number of basic patterns (only five in the classification schema of Chrisomalis 2010), making them recognizable as numbers even in unknown languages and scripts. By comparison, non-numerical signs symbolize their meaning, making them relatively ambiguous regarding their intended semantic and phonetic values (e.g., as the pictograph of a head could mean head, person, or capital). Further, the organization of non-numerical language is much more variable, and context affects both semantic and phonetic value. These factors pressure non-numerical signs to incorporate semantic and phonetic clues that alter their appearance. Thus, while both numerical and non-numerical signs lose iconicity through factors involved in emergent literacy, non-numerical signs lose more (i.e., become more abstract in this sense of the term) than numerical signs do.

§4.5. Abstract can also connote something that has become distilled, refined, or purified to its essential nature, perhaps in the process becoming more accurate and true, or something that has achieved a state more rarified and complex than what preceded it, making it more difficult for the uninitiated to comprehend. Certainly, numbers have changed over the past millennia, and if distilled and truer, they have also become more complicated and difficult to grasp in their totality: Old Babylonian numbers are relatively simple compared to their Greek counterparts, whose foundational ontological role connected the sensible and nonsensible realms, not just for themselves but for all things (Klein 1968); with their modern counterparts, it is not only possible but desirable to prove something as seemingly self-evident and incontrovertible as 1 + 1 = 2 (Peano 1889; Whitehead & Russell 1927). Materiality has been central to this evolutionary development: It collects and consolidates social knowledge and interfaces what a society knows and an individual learns, distributing elaborational effort over space and time (Haas 1996; Hutchins 1995). As the conceptualization of number differs by evolutionary locus, a further distinction can be made between a material form and the concept it represents, not merely because the former makes the latter tangible: At least part of conceptual content relates to the number system, as the relations among numbers are as critical to what numbers are and what they can do as are notes to music and sounds to language (Plato 1892). As numerals (and other material forms) make numbers accessible, their “perceived relationships … are taken as proxies (consciously or unconsciously) for relationships among conceptual elements” (Hutchins 2005: 1562). Material representation makes numerical relations accessible in a way that enhances the visualization of patterns and bypasses psychological constraints (e.g., working memory capacity); the evolutionary mechanism this provides is one in which material properties are as pertinent as mental ones.

§4.6. As numerical relations become more explicit (e.g., not just “greater than” and “plus one” but “11 is 3 more than 8”), they also become more accessible to manipulation. This relates to the sense in which abstract, theoretical, or pure mathematics contrasts with its mundane counterpart, the everyday use of numbers: The former is concerned with numerical relations, the latter with questions of how many and how much, the difference between searching for higher prime numbers and summing a grocery bill. A pure mathematics is said to have developed by the Old Babylonian period (Friberg 2007; Høyrup 2002a, 2002b; Robson 2007, 2008), as discerned through complex calculations with quantities or measurements that could not exist in actuality, making them pure “in substance,” though they remained “applied in form” in dealing with matters like military construction and agricultural yield (Høyrup 1994: 8; emphasis in original). Greek mathematicians, in comparison, investigated knowledge “systematically and for its own sake (or at least without any intentions of application)” (Høyrup 1994: 25; emphasis in original), a distinction Damerow noted in his model. However, Greek concern with conceptual content, definitions, and ontological status was informed by the abstract mathematics developed in Mesopotamia, and it was not limited to numbers or mathematics but rather involved the entire spectrum of scientific thought as it was then known. Thus, while representational separation undoubtedly facilitated the complex and artificial calculations of Mesopotamian mathematicians and contributed to the later conceptual work of the Greeks, the further elaboration of number concept by the latter cannot be ascribed solely to independent mathematical developments but must be contextualized as part of continued change in mathematical thinking and broader change in scientific thought.

§4.7. The terms concrete and abstract have another connotation, familiar in discussions of Ancient Near Eastern numbers: specified or unspecified, or connected (or not) to the objects of which a number is the quantity (e.g., Schmandt-Besserat 1981). To Damerow, the early numerical signs were specified, as they referred to particular commodities, and cuneiform numbers were unspecified, as they did not so refer. However, even the later Greeks lacked unspecified numbers. The everyday numbers used in counting and calculating (arithmos) were so thoroughly identified with the sensible objects they quantified that while a number designating different objects had the same quantity, it differed with respect to the objects it designated: The ten used with horses thus differed from the ten used with dogs (Klein 1968, drawing on Aristotle). Plato’s pure or nonsensible numbers were similarly specified: One was not a number but an indivisible unity, of which the pure numbers, two and higher, were multiples and thus specified (this construct created some difficulty, as the indivisibility of one meant that pure numbers could not be divided into fractions like arithmos could be) (Klein 1968). Against Damerow’s model, this suggests that Greek specified numbers were less abstract than cuneiform unspecified numbers, or that cuneiform numbers were not really unspecified (perhaps in referring to the metrological systems they intermediated; Robson 2008), or that the Mesopotamians may have distinguished, as the Greeks did, the quantity of a number (shared) from its designation (specified). Certainly, Mesopotamian length and area calculations were specified, since continuous extents are ratios of some known measure, not discrete items subject to individuation and enumeration. The idea that number could be unspecified was the work of Renaissance mathematicians like Viète, Stevin, and Descartes, part of a larger reconceptualization that included one, zero, fractions, infinity, and unknown numbers in the same symbolic class as the positive integers and which unified continuous and discrete numeration (Klein 1968; Rotman 1987, 2000). The point is not to reassign abstract numbers to the Renaissance (or indeed, to the late 19th century, where Crossley [1987] suggests numerical abstractness developed suddenly from a purported previous concreteness through work by Dedekind), but to draw attention to the fact that the Mesopotamian numbers represented by the early numerical signs, considered in total across the multiple systems they instantiated, referred to a much broader range of objects than what a tally might designate. This attribute might have been acknowledged as representing abstract numeration had the early numerical signs not been labeled as concrete.

§4.8. Beyond specifying particular things or nothing whatsoever (except perhaps each other), numbers can apply to anything and everything (it is left to the reader to determine whether this is best characterized as specified or not): “For number applies itself to men, angels, actions, thoughts, every thing that either doth exist or can be imagined” (Locke 1690, Book 2, Chapter XVI, Sect. 1). The set of entities over which numbers can range becomes functionally limitless, a significant expansion compared to the relatively few commodities specified by early Mesopotamian numerical signs. This expansion, however, obscures a similar phenomenon in the material instantiation of number, where the incorporation of multiple material forms has three major effects: First, multiple instantiating forms enable comparisons of what they share and, more importantly, where and how they differ (e.g., as tokens were manipulable but numerical impressions were fixed). The contrast between forms (and language) potentializes elaboration, relative to systems with fewer forms (e.g., the Oksapmin body counting system prior to its exposure to Western mathematical practices; Saxe 2012; reinforcement between the ordinal sequence provided by both the single material form and language yielded a stable system). In the Ancient Near East, not only were a variety of forms used, there were multiple numerical systems in contact with each other, whose different organization (e.g., Sumerian sexagesimal; Akkadian and Elamite decimal) would have provided contrasting elements. New material forms provide additional ways to represent and manipulate number concepts, the potential for novel structure, and material contrasts that may serve to highlight differences and foster insight.

§4.9. The concept of number also incorporates attributes from the various material forms used to instantiate it: For example, numerical notations became manipulable once the relations between numbers had been sufficiently explicated and learned and suitable algorithms were formulated. But notations are fixed, not manipulable, which suggests they incorporated the manipulability of the earlier tokens, a development perhaps involving some awareness that what older forms enabled should be possible with newer forms. The concept of number also helps perpetuate these attributes across changes in material form: As their representation on the outsides of bullae indicates, tokens likely preserved the linear ordering by increasing magnitude of fingers and tallies, despite the potential for other organizational schemes (e.g., in a circle rather than a line; random or alternating magnitude; etc.) implied by their manipulability. Further, though once made they were fixed, the notational forms (i.e., the numerical impressions on bullae and envelopes, archaic numerical notations, and cuneiform numbers) were consistently ordered linearly and by increasing magnitude, though they too could have been otherwise organized during the process of manufacture. However, material forms and the concepts they instantiate condition those who use them to things working in certain ways. Familiarity and habituation narrow the range of behaviors possible with newer forms, enabling the structure of older forms to influence the structuring potential of newer forms.

§4.10. Finally, when the concept of number is instantiated by a variety of forms, it becomes in a sense independent of any of them, yet another way of understanding the term “abstract.” To paraphrase Miller (1980: 4) on the independence of the concept money from the many forms it can assume: Numerals are not numbers but a form of number; whatever its real nature, the concept of number is revealed through the form(s) that instantiate(s) it (Overmann 2017). The use of multiple forms implies a concept that has become independent of any particular form, something that is true of the Western number concept: We count with our fingers, make tally marks, use coins (a material form similar to tokens in being manipulable and numerically interrelated), write numbers on paper and chalkboards, type them into calculators and computers, etc. The concept of number encompasses all of these various material forms (and more that have not been listed), along with aspects of only some of them (e.g., linearity; manipulability), characteristics that may not be implicit in every particular form but perpetuated through conceptual content. The potential persistence of tallies and tokens thousands of years after their first appearance in the archaeological records (e.g., Henkelman & Folmer 2016; MacGinnis et al. 2014), the presumed persistence of finger-counting to the point where it appears in the textual record, and indeed, the distribution of numerical value over multiple systems of early numerical signs (including the tokens), suggest that Mesopotamian numbers were similarly distributed across, and thus independent of, the different forms of materiality used to represent and manipulate them, and that this independence perhaps emerged in the Neolithic.

§4.11. In sum, number is abstract in being formed and changed through the cognitive process of abstraction. It is abstract in its intangibility and subject to some abstractness in losing iconicity. It is abstract in the sense that its content changes over time through elaboration, in being applied theoretically, in expanding its range of potential application, and in becoming less dependent on particular material forms. Yet while number is abstract from its inception, it remains bound, however loosely, to the materiality that gives rise to it as concept, that makes it tangible and accessible and manipulable, that stabilizes and makes it generationally persistent, and whose properties inform its character while enabling it to change. Rather than being conceived as being “concrete” at some times and “abstract” at others, number should be acknowledged to have a dual abstract-concrete nature (with the quality “abstract” as stipulated and numerical content, structure, and organization changing as described). With number as a concept that emerges from the interaction of the psychological, behavioral, and material elements of numerical cognition, the “abstract-concrete” distinction collapses.[2]

§5. Related Assumptions
§5.1.
Damerow’s idea that the early numerical signs entailed concrete numbers was derived from their meaning, which was distributed, context-dependent, and specified: In the Neolithic, the numerical meaning of tokens varied geographically and temporally, creating an impression there was no abstract concept of number to unify them (this is compounded by a tendency to label any small clay object as a token; archaeological contexts being ambiguous regarding intended use; among other criticisms; see Englund 1998; Friberg 1994; Zimansky 1993). By the late 4th millennium, numerical signs also distributed their meaning between multiple, commodity-specific systems, in which conventions of shape, size, and order encoded both number and commodity and a particular sign could hold different values (i.e., polyvalency) relative to higher- and lower-value signs (Nissen, Damerow & Englund 1993; also see Fig. 3). Value that was distributed, context-dependent, and specified suggested to Damerow a concrete concept of number. However, specification may have been an improvement over earlier, non-specifying technologies (more on this later). Further, distributed, context-dependent, specified numbers need not be concrete: the question how many? implicitly means how many [what]; 10 can mean ten or two; and both are associated with thoroughly abstract numbers. The idea that distributed, context-dependent specificity signaled concrete numbers is absurd, as it would make those familiar with them “less numerate than the average Sumerian who did not use texts, only number words” (Chrisomalis 2005: 4). And as discussed, the distribution of numerical meaning over multiple representational systems may have signified an abstract concept of number, in the sense of being independent from any particular material form.

figure 3

Fig. 3: Two of over a dozen archaic numeral systems used for counting and representing (top) most objects and (bottom) grain, probably barley. Redrawn from Nissen, Damerow & Englund (1993) without the fractions for System 2. Note that N14 is equal to ten N01 in System 1 but six N01 in System 2; the ability of the same sign to hold different values across systems is called polyvalency. Also note that relative to N34, N45 has a higher value in System 1 but a lower one in System 2; such context-dependent value meant that N48 was equivalent to 600 N01 in System 1 but 1800 N01 in System 2. Context was determined by sign order, the use of signs unique to a particular system (e.g., N50 and N39), and bundling amounts (six or ten N01). Context also specified commodity (e.g., N34 meant barley in System 2 but “humans and animals, dairy and textile products, fish, wooden and stone implements, [or] containers” in System 1; Nissen, Damerow & Englund 1993: 28). Other methods of representing commodity were also used: Container-shaped tokens (e.g., jars for oil) represented number and commodity conjointly through resemblance and unbundled repetition (Damerow & Meinzer 1995). Commodity could also be represented separately from number, perhaps through complex tokens (Schmandt-Besserat 1992a; however, this is the least accepted part of Schmandt-Besserat’s hypothesis; see criticisms by Englund 1998a; Friberg 1994; Zimansky 1993). Other, more ambiguous methods of representing commodity separately from number involved the use of seals or trading context (Englund 1998b; Jasim & Oates 1986); these methods would have identified people known to deal in specific items, commodities that were not otherwise specified in seals or which involved trade relations invisible to archaeological methods.

§5.2. Rather than indicating a concrete number confusing sign with signified, conjoint representation may have simply been the Mesopotamian solution to a common problem, how to represent number and commodity in material form prior to the invention and availability of writing. In traditional societies, when a hunter marks his arm or the ground to count the days he has traveled or the enemies he has killed (Morgan 1852; Pelleschi 1896), he is unlikely to conflate the marks with either but simply represents the quantity of what he counts with the marks and maintains the knowledge of what he counts separately, perhaps in memory or the context of discussion. Granted, without their separation, further elaboration of the representation number and commodity is less likely. However, once the amount and duration of what needs to be remembered exceeds the capacity and persistence of human memory, some more capacious and durable method will be developed, and it may at some point involve representational separation. Other societies have solved the problem similarly to the way the Mesopotamians initially did, by means of encoding quantity, shape, and/or position; these devices include the Peruvian quipu, knotted string systems used in Peru, Bolivia, and Germany, Roman counting board, Chinese and Roman abacus, and Japanese Soroban (Zhang & Norman 1995). None of these has been labeled as representing a particularly concrete notion of number, despite the similarity of their conjoined representation with that of the early numerical signs, impressions, and tokens of the Ancient Near East.

§5.3. The idea that early numerical signs (e.g., tokens, impressions, proto-cuneiform) were used with a restricted numerical lexicon relates to the idea that concrete thinking precluded both concepts of and words for abstract numbers (previously discussed) and to the inexpressiveness of early writing (i.e., the need for greater specificity in non-numerical signs). Sumerian numbers are typically described as a system in which early numerical signs were used with an oral counting sequence of only small quantities, signs for higher quantities like 600 were used without any corresponding vocabulary, and there was no ability to expand spoken numerals systematically before writing was invented (Høyrup 2016). The textual evidence for a numerical lexicon thus requires context: The emergence of phonetic values for lexical and ordinal words (e.g. and respectively, one, thousand and first, thousandth) and grammatical singular-plural distinctions in the 3rd millennium is more likely related to increased expressiveness (greater specificity) in writing, rather than indicating these features had only recently emerged in speech, for three reasons: The recency hypothesis (i.e., the idea that unrestricted lexical numbers emerged in Sumerian only after the invention of proto-cuneiform) and the fact that lexical forms precede grammatical ones (Corbett 2000; Overmann 2015) entail a significantly accelerated timeline at odds with the gradual pace of such grammaticalization generally (Heine 2003; Traugott & Heine 1991). The recency hypothesis also ignores the import of token precursors and the semantic (non-phonetic) sufficiency of numerical representation, which suggest, respectively, the early development of a numerical lexicon and a late emergence for its phonetic representation. Finally, the recency hypothesis cannot account for the differences (e.g., marking method, distinctions expressed, animacy modulation) in Sumerian, Akkadian, and Elamite grammatical number that imply its separate development (i.e., before the significant inter-group contact of the late Neolithic).

§5.4. A restricted lexicon also cannot be confirmed through the frequency of ordinal numbers (Dahl 2015), as higher ordinal terms (e.g., sixth, tenth, hundredth) have a negligible frequency even in numerate languages with expressive scripts. Simply, the writing system’s inability to express numbers phonetically does not entail there were no such words, especially given the semantic sufficiency of numerical representation mentioned previously. Further, while there is some lag between the initial representation of numbers materially (e.g., with fingers, gesture, tallies, etc.) and their linguistic expression, the lag is associated with relatively small, isolated societies, not populations the size and scale of the Ancient Near Eastern Neolithic. No known number systems have a lag the size of the one suspected for the Ancient Near East; rather, the ability to represent numbers in the hundreds materially invariably has a corresponding vocabulary, including an ability to express higher quantities in systematized and regularized ways (Comrie 1989; Greenberg 1978). Thus, early numerical signs for quantities in the hundreds are evidence of an unrestricted numerical lexicon, even if the associated phonetic values remained unrecorded until much later.

§5.5. The assumption that tokens were the initial counting technology used in the Ancient Near East is countered on several grounds. First, there is archaeological evidence of possible tallies in the Upper Paleolithic Levant and known cultural diffusion between the populations that expanded into southern Mesopotamia from the Levant and Zagros Mountains during the Neolithic (Lazaridis et al. 2016; Reese 2002). There is also textual and numerical evidence that implies finger-counting with a relative chronology that likely predates tallies and thus tokens as well. Schmandt-Besserat (1992a) acknowledged both, but she did not address their significance as possible token precursors. Admittedly, both are ambiguous regarding counting. For the artifacts purported to be tallies, there is no definitive way to establish their use in counting, as marks on bones can be made for a variety of other purposes, including record-keeping, divination, music, fiber- or leather-working, and tools of an unknown type (Reese 2002). For fingers (and possibly toes as counting devices), the evidence takes two forms: One post-dates tokens as lexical terms (i.e., five-plus compounds for six through nine; ten- and twenty-cycles in higher lexical numbers) whose preservation had to wait for writing to be invented and then develop both the ability and the need to express the phonetic values of Sumerian number-words; the other consists of the productive cycles of 10 in the Sumerian, Akkadian, and Elamite number systems, ten-ness that typically derives from the use of the fingers in counting (Blažek 1999; Edzard 1980; Englund 1998c, 2004; Friberg 2007; Nissen, Damerow & Englund 1993).[3]

figure 4

Fig. 4: Numerical representational of tallies (left) and tokens (right). In a tally, numerical representation is one-dimensional; total value is achieved by accumulating value along the single dimension. With tokens, there are more relations between numbers: those of sequential plus-one accumulation (the horizontal axis) and those implicit in bundling (the vertical axis); total value is achieved by accumulating value along both dimensions. The two-dimensional structure of tokens implies one-dimensional precursors like tallies and/or fingers.

§5.6. However ambiguous the evidence of fingers and tallies might be, tokens were still unlikely to have been first, on grounds of their complex numerical representation: Tokens were related not just to what they counted but to each other as well, through bundling relations that made a single token of a higher value equal to 2-10 tokens of a lower value; in many (but not all) cases, bundling reflected metrological relations between containers used for the commodities in question (Nissen, Damerow & Englund 1993). In adding a second dimension to their numerical representation (Fig. 4), bundling implies that the tokens were likely preceded by one or more one-dimensional technologies. (A possible counterargument, that tokens simply depicted what they counted, leaves the evidence of finger-counting and possible tallies unexplained.) Bundling also counters the idea that tokens represented one-to-one correspondence, since they were related to each other and not just the commodity they enumerated. In addition, bundling operations (i.e., the exchange of higher- and lower-value tokens to simplify a compilation of tokens to its simplest and most accessible numerical form) necessitated a relative faculty with quantities like six and 10, which exceed the range of perceptual salience (i.e., the so-called subitization constraint) that limits the quantities appreciable without counting to three or four. This in turn implies that the numerical lexicon likely reached numbers that corresponded not only to bundling values (i.e., up to 10) but to the values of compound tokens as well (tens and hundreds), rather than being restricted to subitizable amounts.

§6. Material and Conceptual Change in Ancient Near Eastern Numbers
§6.1.
If the possible evidence of fingers and tallies is accepted, the sequence of counting technologies in the Ancient Near East includes fingers, tallies, tokens, and the various numerical notations. In the analysis presented in Table 2, fingers and notations were treated as if they were material in the same way that physical devices like tallies and tokens are. Typically, fingers are thought of as biological supports to psychological capabilities like working memory, notations as signs and symbols. The assumption entailed that the conceptual boundaries between the body and the material (for fingers), and the material and the psychological (for numerical notations), needed to tolerate a degree of ambiguity in what they delimited. To bridge the ambiguity, Gibson’s (1977, 1979) notion of affordance was used. An affordance is a relation between what an agent is capable of and what its environment enables it to do; here it designates the exploitable properties of a material form used for counting. Analysis of the affordances provided by the different counting technologies then allowed characterization of how they were similar (e.g., fingers and tallies, in influencing structural characteristics like linearity) and how they differed (fingers only, in being part of the body, etc.).

table 2

Table 2: Analysis of affordance similarities and differences

NB: Embodied characteristics are significantly influenced by psychological and physiological traits. Material characteristics are imposed (or enabled) by the material form. Representation: Characteristics applicable to how the material structure represents numerical information. Conceptual change: How the concept of number would have changed in conjunction with material, behavioral, and psychological change.

§6.2. The analysis yielded the insight that new material forms were incorporated because they shared some affordances with older forms and because they brought new affordances that addressed limitations in older forms. New forms also brought new limitations into the system for numbers that eventually motivated the inclusion of new forms, and the contrast between newer and older forms provided elaborational opportunities. Newer forms were often associated with behavioral differences, and in some cases changes in psychological processing (e.g., the shift to knowledge-based calculation would have been associated with recruitment of the parts of the brain involved in recalling arithmetical facts, etc.), that would have affected how numbers were conceptualized. Concurrently, older forms appear to have persisted, both directly as a retained technology for representing and manipulating numbers and indirectly in the way their structure persisted in the way newer forms were used. These insights expand Gallagher’s notion of an “affordance space,” the “range of possibilities provided by any active movement in body or change in environment” delimited not just by the physiology and psychological capacities furnished evolutionarily, the stage of ontogenetic development applying to participating individuals, and the sociocultural practices informing behavioral possibilities (Gallagher 2015), but by the capabilities, limitations, and structuring of the materials used and the concepts themselves as well.

§6.3. Four key transitions in the material sequence are highlighted below: Fingers influenced basic structure; tallies represented the transition to incorporating material culture; tokens represented the emergence of knowledge-based numeration; and written notations enabled numbers to become conceptualized as entities. These are also interactions with material forms that potentialize neural reorganizations (i.e., the neuronal recycling hypothesis of Dehaene & Cohen 2007): For example, knowledge-based numeration implies recruitment of the angular gyrus, which demonstrates activity during the recall of arithmetic facts (Grabner et al. 2009); while parietal activity predominates during the performance of mathematical tasks (Amalric & Dehaene 2016), the frontal lobes also show activity and imply the involvement of executive functions like intentionality and working memory.

§6.3.1. Fingers influence numbers toward linearity and stable order (Gelman & Gallistel 1978), structure that is “essential to most of [numbers’] mathematical properties” (Russell 1920: 29) and which persists across subsequent material forms. As mentioned, the concept of number starts with the recognition that two sets of objects share the same cardinality. Representation of the concept by one of the sets in the comparison, typically the fingers, sets up an initial structuring—by fives and tens; in linear and stable order—as a function of what the hand is as an instantiating material form in interaction with other psychological, physiological, and behavioral capacities: As material device, the hand provides five digits, logical start and stop points in the outer fingers, and accumulation as counting proceeds across the hand. Working memory is limited in the number of items that can be held in active attention and manipulated mentally, necessitating the inclusion of material representations. Finger-counting, like any repetitive motor movement, becomes patterned in ways that maximize its efficiency and automaticity, which in turn reduces demands on attention and working memory and improves the reproducibility, reliability, and accessibility of the numerical information instantiated by the fingers. Language influences counting toward sequentiality through the seriality of the sound stream. While there may indeed be a sort of logical predestination to numerical ordering, numbers may be influenced toward linearity and stable order as much through the use of the hand as a material device as by the functional effectiveness in counting that magnitude ordering provides.

§6.3.2. Given sufficient societal motivation for counting beyond what the hand can provide (e.g., the need for amounts beyond those reasonably accumulated on the fingers; time durations longer than what the hand can feasibly represent), tallies are the kind of device typically incorporated into a number system once the limitations of the hand are encountered (similar material devices include knotted strings, torn leaves, collected pebbles, etc.). Tallies would have marked a key transition, from using the body as a device for counting, to involving material forms not part of the body. Material artifacts are sharable in ways that bodies and behaviors (especially those associated with social status and prestige) are typically not, making the number knowledge instantiated by devices more public and socially permitted, and less private and proscribed, than the number knowledge instantiated by the body. Relative to bodies and behaviors, material artifacts also have a higher plasticity and capacity for being modified to collect and consolidate social knowledge. This is a critical aspect of transmitting information to new individuals and between generations, not only because it makes the information available but because it can reduce acquisition to a matter of learning to use the device, eliminating the need for reinvention and often bypassing the need to master theories and principles.

§6.3.3. Tokens provided access to a more extensive and explicit set of numerical relations, operations, and algorithms for calculating, which are important as they provide the basis for knowledge-based calculating. Where tallies provided a few relations (e.g., plus one, more than, less than, not equal, etc.) and operations (accumulation), tokens provided the relations implicit in bundling values, and operations of accumulation, reduction, grouping, separation, and simplification (respectively, addition, subtraction, multiplication, reciprocals, and bundling-debundling). Tokens also enabled algorithms like the agrimensors’ method of approximating the area of a field, attested as early as 3250 BC in the form of two exercises on a tablet from Uruk, W 19408,76 (Englund 1998c; Nissen, Damerow & Englund 1993; also see Fig. 5). Tokens’ relations of value to each other necessitated that value-relations be learned and associated particular token shapes and sizes with specific values quantified in numerical terms. Tokens nonetheless represented quantity conceived in terms of collections, as tallies had, because they were meaningful only in aggregate, rather than individually.

figure 5

Fig. 5: W 19408,76, an accounting school text dated to 3250-3000 BC, the earliest such known (Nissen, Damerow & Englund 1993; Friberg 2005; Robson 2007). Ninda, iku, and šar were area measures; 1 ninda was about 6 meters, 1 iku = 100 ninda, and 1 šar = 1080 iku or 38.9 km2. The algorithm’s complexity suggests that such calculations, or at least simpler versions of them, were performed with tokens well before the invention of the notational recording represented by the tablet, especially since notations were not initially useful for calculating. The exercises also involved “unrealistically large” surface areas (Englund 1998b: 110) that suggest a pure (non-applied) mathematics was already developing in the late 4th millennium. Line art from Englund 1998b: fig. 85.

§6.3.4. Cuneiform notations enabled numbers to be conceptualized as entities through three critical attributes: They were handwritten, concise, and fixed. Writing by hand trained the brains of scribes to recognize individual notations as objects; this is a neural reorganization that occurs in literacy, as the part of the temporal lobe that recognizes objects, the fusiform gyrus, becomes trained to recognize written marks as if they were objects and to associate them lexically by interaction developed between the fusiform gyrus and the language centers of the brain (reviewed in Overmann 2016b). Second, their concision allowed notations to be individuated, rather than remain collections as tokens were. Concision also enabled large volumes of detailed numerical relations to be recorded in the form of tables (e.g., multiplication tables; tables of reciprocals), which scribes reproduced and learned during training. This in turn yielded more options in calculating, as scribes could consult the tables or recall numerical relations from memory, in addition to performing the calculations with tokens. Concision in recording intermediate and final results would have also supported the development of greater complexity in calculation methods. Most importantly, numerical relations gave individual numbers an identity that would have reinforced their reconceptualization as objects or entities fostered by the neural training effects of handwriting. Third, the notations were fixed, as the impressions and archaic numerals had been, motivating the development of new algorithms that leveraged numerical knowledge to an even greater extent than token-based accounting did, algorithms that drew upon and thus reinforced the knowledge of numerical relations and the conceptualization of numbers in terms of relational identities.

§6.4. Notations provide another reason for reconsidering the abstract-concrete distinction: Usually considered to fall on the “abstract” side, notations remained closely bound to their material realizers, exhibiting a concreteness that is usually obscured by their abstract designation. Yes, they could be written without commodity labels and were manipulated in complex algorithms, functioning as conceptual entities related numerically to similar entities. But commodity labels were understood contextually when omitted, and in calculations notations remained closely tied to practical domains (hence, Høyrup’s [1994] designation of the Babylonian mathematics tradition as subscientific). More interestingly, the numbers represented notationally differed in arithmetical operations in ways that evoke the material forms used for calculation: Babylonian mathematics had, for example, two additions and two subtractions, which differed according to whether the original quantities remained recognizable or not (e.g., in addition performed with commingled tokens, the original quantities would be lost once they joined the pile) (Høyrup 2002a). This contrasts with modern numbers, which achieve the same sums and differences regardless of whether calculations are performed with fingers, abaci, or computers. Which is only to say that Babylonian and modern numbers are different concepts represented by different material forms.

§6.5. What the cuneiform notations ultimately yielded, however, was a semiotic system in which the elements (numbers) were meaningful entities whose identity derived from their identification as objects and the interrelations providing calculational access and complexity. This system informed the later mathematics of the Greeks, who further elaborated the system by considering the patterns made by numerical relations and operations (e.g., odd/even; multiplication sets) (Klein 1968), work built upon the foundation initially established by the Mesopotamians with tokens and tallies. While the Greek elaboration also perhaps shows more clearly a role for ontological and epistemological imagination—why does someone ask what a number is, or whether 1 + 1 will always and under every circumstance yield 2—it also shows that such imagination acts within and at the boundaries of an existing system, elaborating its substance, testing its limits, and taking for granted the ideas and social knowledge received from the work of many earlier hands in the form of materially instantiated knowledge. In such systems in general, there may be a role for Piaget’s ontogenetic effects in providing a familiar mastery that is well positioned to question the system’s parameters, but there is also a significant role for the material component, particularly in numbers, who so happily match material structures’ seemingly limitless potential to instantiate and illuminate novel numerical relations, and the human psychological, behavioral, and physiological abilities that discover and exploit them.

Notes

*    J. Cale Johnson, Dwight Read, Rex Welshon, Robert K. Englund, Steven Chrisomalis, and an anonymous reviewer offered many helpful comments on the initial draft; any remaining errors and omissions are, of course, my own.

1    Piaget envisioned the child’s acquisition of number as a process of developing “biologically predetermined” cognitive structures through environmental interaction; Damerow argued that environmental interaction (particularly with material representations of number) could influence the substance of numerical content (Damerow 1998: 128). With Material Engagement Theory, material structures become a constitutive component of numerical cognition.

2    This is not an argument for retaining the term “abstract,” but rather, a stipulation that “independence” is another aspect of the quality to which “abstract” has historically been applied.

3    The idea that fingers (and possibly toes) were an early material form for Mesopotamian counting is inferred from extant number systems, where the strong somatic basis for numbers manifests as patterning by fives, tens, and twenties. This somatic basis is a function of the neurological interaction between the intraparietal sulcus (the part of the brain implicated in appreciating quantity; e.g., Ardila 2010) and the angular gyrus (the part that “knows” the fingers and supports both finger-counting and calculating; e.g., Roux et al. 2003). Finger-counting spans the gamut of numerical elaboration (i.e., from emerging to highly elaborated systems), while the use of body parts other than the fingers (e.g., toes; other anatomical features) is associated with emerging number systems (especially ones that have not incorporated other material forms). Mesopotamian numbers would have shared these cross-cultural tendencies, as Ancient Near Eastern people are reasonably and plausibly construed to have had five-fingered hands and typical neurological functionality (and indeed, the latter is supported by linguistic evidence). A more detailed discussion is outside the present scope but is planned.

Bibliography

Amalric, Marie & Dehaene, Stanislas
  2016 “Origins of the Brain Networks for Advanced Mathematics in Expert Mathematicians.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 113, 4909-4917.
Ardila, Alfredo
  2010 “On the Evolution of Calculation Abilities.” Frontiers in Evolutionary Neuroscience 2, 1-7.
Blažek, Václav
  1999 Numerals: Comparative Etymological Analyses and Their Implications: Saharan, Nubian, Egyptian, Berber, Kartvelian, Uralic, Altaic and Indo-European Languages. Brno, Czech Republic: Masarykova Univerzita.
Branner, David P.
  2006 “China: Writing System.” In K. Brown, ed., The Encyclopedia of Language and Linguistics. 2nd edition. Amsterdam: Elsevier, pp. 331-341.
Brouwer, Luitzen E. J.
  1981 Brouwer’s Cambridge Lectures on Intuitionism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Chrisomalis, Stephen
  2005 “Evaluating Ancient Numeracy: Social versus Developmental Perspectives on Ancient Mesopotamian Numeration.” Paper delivered to the Annual Meeting of the Jean Piaget Society (Vancouver, British Columbia).
  2010 Numerical Notation: A Comparative History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Comrie, Bernard
  1989 Language Universals and Linguistic Typology, 2nd edition. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
  2013 “Numeral Bases.” In M. S. Dryer & M. Haspelmath, eds., World Atlas of Language Structures Online. Leipzig: Max Planck Institute for Evolutionary Anthropology. http://wals.info/chapter/131.
Conant, Levi L.
  1896 The Number Concept: Its Origin and Development. New York: Macmillan and Co.
Corbett, Greville G.
  2000 Number. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Crossley, John N.
  1987 The Emergence of Number. Singapore: World Scientific.
Dahl, Jacob L.
  2015 “Comment on ‘Numerosity Structures the Expression of Quantity in Lexical Numbers and Grammatical Number’.” Current Anthropology 56, 647-648.
Damerow, Peter
  1988 “Individual Development and Cultural Evolution of Arithmetical Thinking.” In S. Strauss, ed., Ontogeny, Phylogeny, and Historical Development: The Tel Aviv Annual Workshop in Human Development. Norwood, NJ: Ablex Publishing Corporation, pp. 125-152.
  1996a “Number as a Second-Order Concept.” Science in Context 9, 139-149.
  1996b “Prehistory and Cognitive Development.” In M. Killen, ed., Invited Lecture at the Twenty-Fifth Annual Symposium of the Jean Piaget Society Berkeley, June 1 - June 3, 1995. Berlin: Max Planck Institute for the History of Science, pp. 1-37.
  2007 “The Material Culture of Calculation: A Theoretical Framework for a Historical Epistemology for the Concept of Number.” In U. Gellert & E. Jablonka, eds., Mathematisation and Demathematisation: Social, Philosophical and Educational Ramifications. Rotterdam: Sense Publishers, pp. 19-56.
  2010 Abstraction and Representation: Essays on the Cultural Evolution of Thinking. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer Academic.
  2012 “The Origins of Writing and Arithmetic.” In J. Renn, ed., The Globalization of Knowledge in History. Berlin: Max Planck Research Library for the History and Development of Knowledge, pp. 153-173.
Damerow, Peter & Meinzer, Hans-Peter
  1995 “Computertomografische Untersuchung Ungeöffneter Archaischer Tonkugeln Aus Uruk, W 20987,9, W 20987,11 und W 20987,12.” BagM 26, 7-33.
Dasen, Pierre R.
  1994 “Culture and Cognitive Development from a Piagetian Perspective.” In W. J. Lonner & R. S. Malpass, eds., Psychology and Culture. Boston, MA: Allyn and Bacon, pp. 145-149.
Dehaene, Stanislas & Cohen, Laurent
  2007 “Cultural Recycling of Cortical Maps.” Neuron 56, 384-398.
Dreyfus, Tommy
  1991 “Advanced Mathematical Thinking Processes.” In D. O. Tall, ed., Advanced Mathematical Thinking. New York: Kluwer, pp. 25-41.
Edzard, Dietz Otto
  1980 “Sumerisch 1 Bis 10 in Ebla.” Studi Eblaiti 3, 121-127.
Englund, Robert K.
  1998a “Review: Denise Schmandt-Besserat, How Writing Came About.” Written Language and Literacy 1, 257-261.
  1998b “Proto-Elamite.” In Encyclopædia Iranica 8/3. Cosa Mesa, CA: Mazda Publishers, pp. 325-330.
  1998c “Texts from the Late Uruk Period.” In J. Bauer, R. K. Englund & M. Krebernik, eds., Mesopotamien: Späturuk-Zeit und Frühdynastische Zeit. Freiburg, Switzerland: Universitätsverlag, pp. 15-233.
  2004 “The State of Decipherment of Proto-Elamite.” In S. D. Houston, ed., The First Writing: Script Invention as History and Process. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 100-149.
Epps, Patience et al.
  2012 “On Numeral Complexity in Hunter-Gatherer Languages.” Linguistic Typology 16, 41-109.
Fauconnier, Giles
  1997 Mappings in Thought and Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ferrari, Pier L.
  2003 “Abstraction in Mathematics.” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological Sciences 358 , 1225-1230.
Frege, Gottlob
  1953 The Foundations of Arithmetic: A Logical-Mathematical Investigation into the Concept of Number. 2nd revised edition. J. L. Austin, trans. New York: Harper & Brothers.
Friberg, Jöran
  1994 “Preliterate Counting and Accounting in the Middle East: A Constructively Critical Review of Schmandt-Besserat’s Before Writing.” OLZ 89, 477-489.
  2005 Unexpected Links between Egyptian and Babylonian Mathematics. Singapore: World Scientific.
  2007 A Remarkable Collection of Babylonian Mathematical Texts. Sources and Studies in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences. New York: Springer Science+Business Media, LLC.
Gallagher, Shaun
  2015 “Doing the Math: Calculating the Role of Evolution and Enculturation in the Origins of Geometrical and Mathematical Reasoning.” Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology 119, 341-346.
Gelman, Rochel & Gallistel, C. Randy
  1978 The Child’s Understanding of Number. Cambridge, MA: The President and Fellows of Harvard College.
Gibson, James J.
  1977 “The Theory of Affordances.” In R. Shaw & J. Bransford, eds., Perceiving, Acting, and Knowing: Toward an Ecological Psychology. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum, pp. 127-143.
  1979 The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin.
Glassner, Jean-Jacques
  2000 The Invention of Cuneiform: Writing in Sumer. Z. Bahrani & M. van de Mieroop, trans. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Gowers, Timothy
  2002 Mathematics: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gowers, Timothy, ed.
  2008 The Princeton Companion to Mathematics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Grabner, Roland H. et al.
  2009 “To Retrieve or to Calculate? Left Angular Gyrus Mediates the Retrieval of Arithmetic Facts during Problem Solving.” Neuropsychologia 47, 604-608.
Greenberg, Joseph H.
  1978 “Generalizations about Numeral Systems.” In J. H. Greenberg, ed., Universals of Human Language. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, pp. 249-295.
Haas, Christina
  1996 Writing Technology: Studies on the Materiality of Literacy. New York: Routledge.
Heine, Bernd
  2003 “Grammaticalization.” In B. D. Joseph & R. D. Janda, eds., The Handbook of Historical Linguistics. Malden, MA: Blackwell, pp. 575-601.
Henkelman, Wouter F. M., & Folmer, Margaretha L.
  2016 “Your Tally Is Full! On Wooden Credit Records in and after the Achaemenid Empire.” In K. Kleber & R. Pirngruber, eds., Silver, Money, and Credit: A Tribute to Robartus J. van Der Spek on the Occasion of His 65th Birthday. Leiden: Nederlands Instituut voor het Nabije Oosten, pp. 133-239.
Henrich, Joseph, Heine, Steven J. & Norenzayan, Ara
  2010 “The Weirdest People in the World?” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33, 61‒135.
Høyrup, Jens
  1994 In Measure, Number, and Weight: Studies in Mathematics and Culture. SUNY Series in Science, Technology, and Society. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.
  2002a Lengths, Widths, Surfaces: A Portrait of Old Babylonian Algebra and Its Kin. New York: Springer.
  2002b “A Note on Old Babylonian Computational Techniques.” Historia Mathematica 29, 193-198.
  2016 “Embedding: Multipurpose Device for Understanding Mathematics and Its Development, or Empty Generalization?” Ganita Bhāratī 38, 1-29.
Hutchins, Edwin
  1995 Cognition in the Wild. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
  2005 “Material Anchors for Conceptual Blends.” Journal of Pragmatics 37, 1555-1577.
Ifrah, Georges
  2000 The Universal History of Numbers: From Prehistory to the Invention of the Computer. D. Bellos et al., trans. New York: John Wiley & Sons, Inc.
Inhelder, Barbel & Piaget, Jean
  1958 The Growth of Logical Thinking: From Childhood to Adolescence. New impression A. Parsons & S. Milgram, trans. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul PLC.
Jasim, Sabah A. & Oates, Joan
  1986 “Early Tokens and Tablets in Mesopotamia: New Information from Tell Abada and Tell Brak.” World Archaeology 17, 348-362.
Klein, Jacob
  1968 Greek Mathematical Thought and the Origin of Algebra. E. Brann, trans. New York: Dover Publications, Inc.
Kline, Morris
  1967 Mathematics for the Nonmathematician. New York: Dover Publications, Inc.
Lazaridis, Iosif et al.
  2016 “Genomic Insights into the Origin of Farming in the Ancient Near East.” Nature 536, 419-424.
Lévy-Bruhl, Lucien
  1910 Les fonctions mentales dans les sociétés inférieures. Paris: Librairie Félix Alcan.
  1927 L’âme primative. Paris: Librairie Félix Alcan.
Linnebo, Øystein
  2013 “Platonism in the Philosophy of Mathematics.” In E. N Zalta, ed., Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http: //plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2013/entries/platonism-mathematics/.
Locke, John
  1690 An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. 1854 print. Philadelphia: Hayes & Zell.
MacGinnis, John et al.
  2014 “Artefacts of Cognition: The Use of Clay Tokens in a Neo-Assyrian Provincial Administration.” Cambridge Archaeological Journal 24, 289-306.
Malafouris, Lambros
  2010 “Grasping the Concept of Number: How Did the Sapient Mind Move beyond Approximation?” In C. Renfrew & I. Morley, eds., The Archaeology of Measurement: Comprehending Heaven, Earth and Time in Ancient Societies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 35-42.
  2013 How Things Shape the Mind: A Theory of Material Engagement. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Martzloff, Jean-Claude
  1997 A History of Chinese Mathematics. S. S. Wilson, trans. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.
Mattessich, Richard
  1994 “Archaeology of Accounting and Schmandt-Besserat’s Contribution.” Accounting, Business & Financial History 4, 5-28.
Miller, Henry
  1980 “Money and How It Gets That Way.” Challenge: The Magazine of Economic Affairs 23, 3-5.
Morgan, John
  1852 The Life and Adventures of William Buckley: Thirty-Two Years a Wanderer amongst the Aborigines of the Then Unexplored Country around Port Phillip, Now the Province of Victoria, 19th edition. Adelaide: Griffin Press.
Neugebauer, Otto E.
  1957 The Exact Sciences in Antiquity, 2nd edition. New York: Dover.
Nicolopoulou, Ageliki
  1997 “The Invention of Writing and the Development of Numerical Concepts in Sumeria: Some Implications for Developmental Psychology.” In M. Cole, Y. Engestrom & O. Vasquez, eds., Mind, Culture, and Activity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 205-240.
Nissen, Hans J.
  1986 “The Archaic Texts from Uruk.” World Archaeology 17, 317-334.
Nissen, Hans J., Damerow, Peter & Englund, Robert K.
  1993 Archaic Bookkeeping: Early Writing and Techniques of Economic Administration in the Ancient Near East. P. Larsen, trans. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Oesterdiekhoff, Georg W.
  2016 “Is a Forgotten Subject Central to the Future Development of Sciences? Jean Piaget on the Interrelationship between Ontogeny and History.” Personality and Individual Differences 98, 118-126.
Overmann, Karenleigh A.
  2015 “Numerosity Structures the Expression of Quantity in Lexical Numbers and Grammatical Number.” Current Anthropology 56, 638-653.
  2016a Materiality in Numerical Cognition: Material Engagement Theory and the Counting Technologies of the Ancient Near East. Doctoral thesis, University of Oxford.
  2016b “Beyond Writing: The Development of Literacy in the Ancient Near East.” Cambridge Archaeological Journal 26, 285-303.
  2017 “Concepts and How They Get That Way.” Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1-16. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-017-9545-8
di Paolo, Ezequiel A., Rohde, Marieke & De Jaegher, Hanne
  2010 “Horizons for the Enactive Mind: Values, Social Interaction, and Play.” In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne & E. A. Di Paolo, eds., Enaction: Toward a New Paradigm for Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, pp. 33-87.
Peano, Giuseppe
  1889 Arithmetices principia: nova methodo Exposita. Rome: Fratres Bocca.
Peirce, Charles S.
  1906 “Prolegomena to an Apology for Pragmaticism.” The Monist 16, 492-546.
Pelleschi, Giovanni
  1896 “The Mataco Indians and Their Language.” Boletin del Instituto Geográfico Argentino 17-18. Buenos Aires: Imp. “La Buenos Aries.”
Piaget, Jean
  1928 “Logique Génétique et Sociologie.” Revue Philosophique de la France et de l’Étranger 105, 167-205.
  1937 The Construction of Reality in the Child. M. Cook, trans. New York: Basic Books.
  1952 “The Child’s Conception of Number.” C. Gattegno & F. M. Hodgson, trans. Jean Piaget: Selected Works vol. II. Abingdon, UK: Routledge.
Plato
  1892 Philebus. In The Dialogues of Plato: Parmenides, Theaetetus, Sophist, Statesman, Philebus. 3rd edition. B. Jowett, trans. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Powell, Marvin A.
  1971 Sumerian Numeration and Metrology. Doctoral dissertation, University of Minnesota.
Reese, David S.
  2002 “On the Incised Cattle Scapulae from the East Mediterranean and Near East.” Bonner Zoologische Beitrage 50, 183-198.
Robson, Eleanor
  2007 “Mesopotamian Mathematics.” In V. Katz, ed., The Mathematics of Egypt, Mesopotamia, China, India, and Islam: A Sourcebook. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, pp. 57-186.
  2008 Mathematics in Ancient Iraq: A Social History. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Rosen, Gideon
  2014 “Abstract Objects.” In E. N. Zalta, ed., Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http: //plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/abstract-objects/.
Rotman, Brian
  1987 Signifying Nothing: The Semiotics of Zero. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
  2000 Mathematics as Sign: Writing, Imagining, Counting. Writing Science. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Roux, Franck-Emmanuel et al.
  2003 “Writing, Calculating, and Finger Recognition in the Region of the Angular Gyrus: A Cortical Stimulation Study of Gerstmann Syndrome.” Journal of Neurosurgery 99, 716-727.
Russell, Bertrand
  1920 Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy, 2nd edition. London: George Allen & Unwin, Ltd.
Saxe, Geoffrey B.
  2012 Cultural Development of Mathematical Ideas. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Schmandt-Besserat, Denise
  1977 An Archaic Recording System and the Origin of Writing. Malibu, CA: Undena Publications.
  1978 “The Earliest Precursor of Writing.” Scientific American 238/6, 50-59.
  1981 “From Tokens to Tablets: A Re-Evaluation of the So-Called ‘Numerical Tablets’.” Visible Language 15, 321-344.
  1982 “The Emergence of Recording.” American Anthropologist, New Series 84, 871-878.
  1986 “The Origins of Writing: An Archaeologist’s Perspective.” Written Communication 3, 31-45.
  1992a Before Writing: From Counting to Cuneiform. 2 vols. Austin, TX: University of Texas Press.
  1992b How Writing Came About. Austin, TX: University of Texas Press.
  2010 “The Token System of the Ancient Near East: Its Role in Counting, Writing, the Economy and Cognition.” In C. Renfrew & I. Morley, eds., The Archaeology of Measurement: Comprehending Heaven, Earth and Time in Ancient Societies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 27-34.
  2016 “The Earliest Precursor of Writing.” In D. Crowley & P. Heyer, eds., Communication in History: Technology, Culture, Society, 6th edition. New York: Routledge, pp. 1-16.
Sfard, Anna & Linchevski, Liora
  1994 “The Gains and the Pitfalls of Reification? The Case of Algebra.” Educational Studies in Mathematics 26, 191-228.
Thureau-Dangin, François
  1921 “Numération et métrologie sumériennes.” RA 18, 123-142.
Tompack, Richard S.
  1978 A Comparative Semitic Lexicon of the Phoenician and Punic Languages. Missoula, MT: Scholar’s Press.
Traugott, Elizabeth C. & Heine, Bernd
  1991 “Introduction.” In E. C. Traugott & B. Heine, eds., Approaches to Grammaticalization, vol. II: Focus on Types of Grammatical Markers. Amsterdam: John Benjamins, pp. 1-14.
Vaiman, Aizik A.
  1961 Sumero-Babylonian Mathematics in the Third to First Millennia BCE. Moscow: Izdatel’stvo Vostocnoj Literatury.
Vogel, Kurt
  1959 Vorgriechische Mathematik, vol. II. Die Mathematik der Babylonier. Mathematische Studienhefte 2. Hannover: Hermann Schroedel.
Whitehead, Alfred N. & Russell, Bertrand
  1927 Principia Mathematica, vol. II. 2nd edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zhang, Jiajie, & Norman, Donald A.
  1995 “A Representational Analysis of Numeration Systems.” Cognition 57, 271-295.
Zimansky, Paul
  1993 “Review of Denise Schmandt-Besserat’s Before Writing, vols. I-II.” Journal of Field Archaeology 20, 513-517.

Version: 8 June 2018  

Cite this Article
Overmann, Karenleigh A. 2018. “Updating the Abstract-Concrete Distinction in Ancient Near Eastern Numbers.” Cuneiform Digital Library Journal 2018 (1). https://cdli.mpiwg-berlin.mpg.de/articles/cdlj/2018-1.
Overmann, Karenleigh A. (2018). Updating the Abstract-Concrete Distinction in Ancient Near Eastern Numbers. Cuneiform Digital Library Journal, 2018(1). https://cdli.mpiwg-berlin.mpg.de/articles/cdlj/2018-1
Overmann, Karenleigh A. (2018) “Updating the Abstract-Concrete Distinction in Ancient Near Eastern Numbers,” Cuneiform Digital Library Journal, 2018(1). Available at: https://cdli.mpiwg-berlin.mpg.de/articles/cdlj/2018-1 (Accessed: March 29, 2024).
@article{Overmann2018Updating,
	note = {[Online; accessed 2024-03-29]},
	address = {Oxford; Berlin; Los Angeles},
	author = {Overmann,  Karenleigh A.},
	journal = {Cuneiform Digital Library Journal},
	number = {1},
	year = {2018},
	publisher = {Cuneiform Digital Library Initiative},
	title = {Updating the {Abstract}-{Concrete} {Distinction} in {Ancient} {Near} {Eastern} {Numbers}},
	volume = {2018},
}

TY  - JOUR
AU  - Overmann,  Karenleigh A.
DA  - 2018///
PY  - 2018
ET  - 2021/6/18/
ID  - cdlj-2018-1
IS  - 1
J2  - CDLJ
SN  - 1540-8779
T2  - Cuneiform Digital Library Journal
TI  - Updating the Abstract-Concrete Distinction in Ancient Near Eastern Num
bers
UR  - https://cdli.mpiwg-berlin.mpg.de/articles/cdlj/2018-1
VL  - 2018
Y2  - 2024/3/29/
ER  - 
This website uses essential cookies that are necessary for it to work properly. These cookies are enabled by default.